The Daily Maverick recently published an opinion piece by Professor Pierre de Vos of the University of Cape Town in which he laments what he calls the “Mpofu-fication of politics and ethics” and even of universities.
As examples of this “Mpofu-fication”, he points to two recent review applications against decisions taken by the councils of the University of Stellenbosch and the University of Cape Town. He describes these applications as examples of lawfare, which he appears to define as litigation by “litigants with deep pockets” aimed at reviewing and setting aside “decisions with a strong political, social or ethical dimension” taken by state and public institutions. One purpose of lawfare, he says, is “to embroil an opponent in long and costly litigation and to delay the implementation of a decision”. The implication is that persons or organisations that engage in “lawfare” are abusing legal process – he claims, for example, that such litigants have “access to enormous resources”, and labels these particular two applications as “mischief”.
This is surprising in light of the fact that he co-authored a chapter in a recent book entitled Queer Lawfare in Africa: Legal Strategies in Contexts of LGBTIQ+ Criminalisation and Politicisation (edited by Adrian Jjuuko, Siri Gloppen, Alan Msosa and Frans Viljoen). In that book, lawfare is defined very differently, as “long-term battles over heated social and political issues, where actors on different sides employ strategies using rights, law and courts as tools and arenas”. This definition explicitly avoids viewing lawfare as an abuse of law and litigation for political ends, and avoids judging the moral correctness of the goal of the litigation. Against this background, the book explores the ways in which both “pro- and anti-queer” activists and states have used legislation and litigation to advance their goals. This is of course particularly important in societies where majority governments have introduced legislation that criminalises same-sex relationships.
In contrast, Professor de Vos here creates the impression that, like the tactics of Dali Mpofu SC and some of his clients, these two applications are sinister or otherwise objectionable and therefore ‘bad’, and are unusual or at least somehow different from ‘good’ review applications. This is a startling proposition. As Professor de Vos surely knows, an application to review the decision or action of any state or public institution is always available to anyone able to demonstrate that their rights are infringed by the decision or action, and it is for a court to decide whether the grounds of review raised are valid.
The right to administrative justice, including the right to fair procedure and reasonable action on the basis of a consideration of all relevant factors, is enshrined in the Constitution for good reasons. These include the danger, in a complex and diverse society, of majority decisions infringing the rights of any individuals or groups, including vulnerable minorities. Similarly, the Constitutional Court has created what is called a legality review, grounded in the Constitution, which enables our courts to test the rationality of such majority decisions. This is a fundamental aspect of a constitutional state. The sociologist Bruno Latour has described this power of courts, developed over centuries, as a defence against “tyrannical power”.
The question is not whether a particular application is morally right or wrong, and therefore ‘good’ or ‘bad’. A review application does not have to accord with the moral position of the majority or a decision-maker. In any event, how could we possibly provide a principled version of such a moral test for review applications? Good and reasonable people may well disagree in good faith about moral questions, and they are not for courts to decide.